Some Remarks on Conceptualization and Transcendent Experience
Thusness commented: "It is a good article... ...In the article there is
no obsession or singling out clarity as independent and existing by
itself. "Being" here is understood within/from the context of anatta,
process, verb, no locus and without agent. His term of "being" is not to
single out from the ever dynamics of appearance but rather understood
from the standpoint of non-action. Would be better if there is
integration of total exertion (dependent origination) into it; makes the
article more complete."
http://www.evertype.com/misc/vitakka.html
|
||
Some remarks on conceptualization and transcendent experience in the TheravÄ�da tradition, with two notes on translationMichael EversonThis paper, written originally in 1988, was an excursion into theology -- or perhaps “noetology”. It was an attempt at commentary proper, rather than at disinterested analysis.It is a basic tenet of Buddhism that suffering arises from false notions of self. Individuals perceive themselves as separate entities, autonomous yet dependent on their world, experiencing change and continuity. The uniqueness of each moment of existence is distorted by the filter of a self which categorizes and interprets those moments, judging them good or bad and fighting a useless battle to keep the good and shun the bad. The nexus for the introduction of false notions of self into experience is the point at which experience is conceptualized. Enlightened consciousness results when these false notions are no longer imposed upon the perceptual process. It cannot be said that the Buddhist description of conceptualization is
without its difficulties. Indeed, a Buddhist description ofanything is
much entangled in relationships: just as any event in the world depends
on a nigh infinite series of causes, and engenders a nigh infinite
series of effects, so does a light shone on any facet of Buddhist
epistemology shine and reflect off of each other facet. It is difficult
to pluck one string of the sitar without causing the sympathetic strings
into resonance as well. Still, conceptualization, and its relation to
conditioned and enlightened consciousness, is central to Buddhism --
both to its taxonomy of the problem of existence and to its soteriology.
An investigation of that relation will suggest a reëvaluation of
notions of action and being.
Buddhism might be described as a kind of cure to the disease of dukkha, of ‘suffering’ or ‘unsatisfactoriness’. Existence (bhava) is an ongoing process of becoming, manifest in its constituents (aá¹…ga). The natural (or ideal) condition for the mind is a calm flow (bhavaá¹…ga-sota),
through which (around which, in which) the constituents of becoming
interact harmoniously in an “experiential stream” of what is as it is. Nyanatiloka remarks that bhavá¹£aá¹…ga-sota is explained in the Abhidhamma commentaries as the foundation or condition (kaá¹�raṇa) of existence (bhava), as the sine qua non of life, having the nature of a process, lit. a flux or stream (sota). [Nyanatiloka 1980:38]
Conceptualization impedes the harmonious flow of bhavaá¹…ga-sota. It is a process for ordering stimuli to consciousness, convenient for interaction with the world, but, apparently, not essential once
the world has been investigated. Bondage to concepts is considered to
be an inevitable consequence of the process of conceptualization because
of the fiction of the self, and that bondage to concepts leads to expectation and denial, the causes of dukkha. A review of the process leading up to conceptualization will be helpful here.
The immediate precursors to conceptualization have been classified as a purely impersonal, causal process. In the Madhupiṇá¸�ika-sutta, the venerable Kaccaá¹�na sums up his understanding of the Buddha’s teaching:
‘And, brothers, the mind and mental objects are the cause for the arising of mental consciousness. The meeting of the three is sense contact; feelings are the result of that contact; what one feels one perceives; what one perceives one reasons about; what one reasons about one differentiates; what one differentiates is the origin of the sign of perceptions and obstructions which assail a man with regard to mental objects to be comprehended by the mind, in the past, the future, and the present.’ Interaction between one of the sense-bases (the five senses and the
mind) and an object gives rise to the attentive faculty of
consciousness, that is, of awareness of objects. The meeting of the
three is contact (phassa); from this contact arises sensation or feeling (vedan�).
The living being with functioning sense organs must interact with
objects, become conscious of them through contact, and feel or sense
them. When the ego intrudes and makes the connection “I experience this
object”, the process loses its impersonality, and becomes first a kind
of deliberate and conscious, then a subconscious and automatic activity,
conditioned by karmic predisposition. KaccÄ�na’s description points to
this shift from impersonal to personal in his movement from a simple
ablative construction to the inflected personal verb: “PhassapaccayÄ� vedanÄ�, yaá¹� vedeti taá¹� sañjÄ�nÄ�ti” ‘From the condition of contact [arises] feeling; what one feels, one perceives’. Suddenly it is an individual person (puggala) who experiences sensation; and when he does, he perceives, knows, or recognizes (compare sañjÄ�nÄ�ti with Latin cÅ�gnÅ�scit). A person has arisen here out of nonperson: attÄ� out ofanattÄ�.
That ego, once established with its faculties of memory and volition,
will evaluate its sensations in terms of itself; it will judge, and
desire. That ego is a confluence of material and mental processes, and,
apart from them, has no real existence.
Conceptualization arises from perception. “Yaá¹� sañjÄ�nÄ�ti taá¹� vitakketi” ‘What
one perceives, one reflects on’. This is indicative of the insidious
nature of the ego to take the original subjective experience and
“objectivize” it. Though each object, contact, and sensation be unique,
the ego takes them only in relation to itself and its past, present, and
future experience and needs. The concepts (vitakk�) which arise
through perception tend toward proliferation, for the ego becomes
attached to them. Conceptions become preconceptions, and the whole
scheme is filled with error.
The Buddha was concerned about the detrimental nature of attachment to
speculative views of existence and of the Transcendent. The problem is
not whether or not the views themselves have validity, for it is clear
that they do, depending on, and with respect to, the particular point of
view. “The fact that existence is a relative concept is often
overlooked by the worldling.” [ÑÄ�ṇananda 1974:20] It is axiomatic that
the frog knows what the tadpole cannot; but the question here is whether
or not the tadpole’s point of view is wise, and the Buddhist approach
would be to say that no point of view is worthwhile unless it is a view which encompasses reality as it is. That view is impersonal. From the Sutta-nip�ta:
“‘mantÄ� asmÄ« ’ti sabbam uparundhe, yÄ� kÄ�ci taṇhÄ� ajjhattaá¹�, tÄ�saá¹� vinayÄ� sadÄ� sato sikkhe.” [916 (1913:179)] ‘“He should”, said the Lord, “break up the root of these signs of obstruction,[1] the notion ‘I am the thinker’. Whatever his subjective desires, he trains himself to give them up, always mindful in his discipline.”’ It should be noted that both E. M. Hare [Sutta-nipÄ�ta 1944:134] and Hammalava Saddhatissa [Sutta-nipÄ�ta 1985:107] have mistranslated mantÄ� asmi as ‘all the thoughts “I am”’ and ‘all thought of “I am”’ respectively. A better reading would have mantÄ� <mantar ‘thinker’ (< Sanskrit *mantá¹›) and take the deictic ’ti as setting off the phrase mantÄ� asmi as translated above. (Cf. Neumann’s translation “Ich bin’s, der denkt”, ‘I am the one who thinks’. [Sutta-nipÄ�ta 1911:299]) The Commentary to the Sutta-nipÄ�ta, however, explains this phrase by mantÄ�ya:
‘...from this [obstruction] comes the root, the impurities which begin with ignorance: this root of the signs of obstruction is ‘I am’, which results in pride, and he should break up all [this] by wisdom, whatever the subjective desires that should arise, for/of these he trains himself to give up, ever mindful, he should discipline himself, being one whose attention is firm.’ Here the dative mantÄ�ya would also prove difficult for Hare and Saddhatissa’s readings, where we should expect *manÄ� asmi (formanÄ�ya asmi) ‘of the thought “I am”, since we have mano ‘thought’ opposed to mantÄ� ‘wisdom’, as I think the Commentary has it, or even manta (< Sanskrit mantra) ‘charm, doctrine, Holy Scripture’. [Cf. Childers 1875:238-39, and Rhys Davids & Stede 1979:520-22] In any case, I find the present suggested reading more in keeping with the spirit and the sense of the intent of the text, and with the goals of the tradition generally.[2] It is the conceptual attachment of agent to action (yaá¹� maññati taá¹� mantar), resulting from the initial separation of agent from action, which the Buddha attacks in the KÄ�lakÄ�rÄ�ma-sutta, not whether or not there exists a thinker at all. It is true that identification with (or even the ‘real’ existence of) the personal ego is denied elsewhere by the Buddha:
‘...for the noble learned disciple, ignorance is abandoned and knowledge arises. From this cleansing of ignorance and coming into existence of knowledge, his “I am” is no more, his “This I exists” is no more, his “I will be, I will not be, I will have form, I will not have form, I will be conscious, I will be unconscious, I will be neither conscious nor unconscious” is no more.’ Yet there is no suggestion that a universal (albeit VedÄ�ntist) ontological interpretation of aham asmi ‘I am’ would be rejected, though such a rejection could be inferred, I think, in the readings of Hare and Saddhatissa. J. G. Jennings has remarked that “[t]he an-attadoctrine so strongly emphasized by [Gotama] declares the transience of individuality, yet insists upon an ultimate or fundamental unity”. [1974:571] While the PÄ�li commentarial tradition would doubtless reject a VedÄ�ntist claim of an essential unity to Reality, I see no reason to think that a radically non-attached, Liberated notion of “I am” is instrinsically inconsistent with Buddhist teachings. Pure being is neither conceived nor attached, It just Is, and if there is for “me” only “being”, then, it seems, “I am”.[3] The conceptual attachment of agent to action results from an initial (erroneous) separation of agent from action. The source of the delusion standing in the way of Liberation (papañcasaá¹�khÄ�) is the personal notion “I am a thinker” (mantÄ� asmi). Mindfulness is the method by which one learns the process of letting go (vinaya);
that process begins with the elimination of attachment to the things
perceived (pleasure, pain, desire, dislike) and culminates in the
elimination of attachment to the identification with the notion that
there is in fact a perceiver apart from the perception. This process of
detachment from ego is admittedly difficult to describe, and it may be
fruitless to attempt to do so. What may be more fruitful is to
investigate the effects precipitated by that process. By and large, they
derive from a fundamental revision of the process leading up to
conceptualization, and from the removal of the causes leading to
conceptual proliferation and egoistic “ownership” of experience. The Sutta-nipÄ�tadescribes the one who has managed this:
yaá¹� kiñci diá¹á¹haá¹� va sutaá¹� mutaá¹� vÄ�, sa pannabhÄ�ro muni vippayutto na kappiyo nÅ«parato na patthiyo” ti BhagavÄ� ti. [914 (1913:178)] ‘“He who has discarded all theories about anything seen or heard or conceived is a monk who is enlightened and liberated; there is no rule, no abstention, no desire for himself”, said the Lord.’ What is the character of the impersonal viewpoint? In the KÄ�lakÄ�rÄ�ma-sutta, transcendent experience is characterized quite comprehensively:
‘Thus, O monks, the TathÄ�gata, having seen whatever is to be seen, does not conceive of what is seen; he does not conceive of what has not been seen; he does not conceive of that which must yet be seen; he does not conceive of anyone who sees. Having heard whatever is to be heard, he does not conceive of what is heard; he does not conceive of what has not been heard; he does not conceive of that which must yet be heard; he does not conceive of anyone who hears. Having felt whatever is to be felt, he does not conceive of what is felt; he does not conceive of what has not been felt; he does not conceive of that which must yet be felt; he does not conceive of anyone who feels. Having understood whatever is to be understood, he does not conceive of what is understood; he does not conceive of what has not been understood; he does not conceive of that which must yet be understood; he does not conceive of anyone who understands.’
Diá¹á¹haá¹� na maññatÄ« ti taá¹� diá¹á¹haá¹� rÅ«pÄ�yatanaá¹� ahaá¹� mahÄ�janena diá¹á¹ham eva passÄ�mÄ« ti taṇhÄ�mÄ�nadiá¹á¹hÄ«hi na maññati. [IV.iii.4 (1936: III:39)] ‘Daá¹á¹hÄ� daá¹á¹habbaá¹� means “having seen what is to be seen”. Diá¹á¹haá¹� na maññati means “I see the thing seen which is even seen by the people”; one does not conceive {of it} by desires or conceits or opinions’ [i.e., he does not conceptualize about it].) What is there, then? Just seeing, hearing, feeling, or understanding.
There is no agent, no patient, no recipient, no locus: only the verb,
the process, or rather, the proceeding. To be enlightened is not to be or to do any thing: it
is only being, or doing. This is admittedly circular, and it is
proverbial to any student of mysticism--and certainly recognized by the
Buddhist tradition itself--that little can besaid which can give
any real sense of what goes on in transformed consciousness. Buddhism
offers nonetheless its own kind of description, always tending toward
the practical, toward the causes which will bring about the Liberation
itself: that is, toward the empiric. The path to Liberation is twofold:
moving away from deluded action, and moving toward wise action.
It is all the more significant for its corollary that the entire process [of cause and effect] could be made to cease progressively by applying the proper means. Negatively put, the spiritual endeavor to end all suffering, is a process of ‘starving’ the conditions of their respective ‘nutriments’ (Ä�hÄ�rÄ�), as indicated by the latter half of the formula of Dependent Arising. However, there are enough instances in the PÄ�li Canon to show that it is quite legitimate to conceive this receding process too, positively as a progress in terms of wholesome mental states. [ÑÄ�ṇananda 1974:46-47] The eradication of conceptualization and the cultivation of a
dispassionate, impersonal observation is the key to Liberation.
“Ever-becoming and ever-ceasing-to-be are endless action.... Ceaseless
action is the Universe.” [Merrell-Wolff 1973:247] Since the being
embodied must be a part of such action, his hope must be to loose
himself from the bounds of causal action: he must seek Liberation. Perhaps it is not so ironic that in order to do so, he must realize that there is nothing but action; for then he is, so says the Buddha, free.
Notes[1] I prefer here the reading of papañca as ‘obstruction’ or ‘hinderance’ to the commonly met with ‘obsession’. Here I follow Rhys Davies’ suggestion that papañca is at least semantically related to *papadya ‘what is in front of the feet’, where he compares Latinimpedimentum (though Sanskrit prapadya should give PÄ�li papajja). [Rhys Davies 1979:412] An obsession is an obstruction, but not all obstructions are obsessions. Cf. also above, in the passage taken from the Madhupiṇá¸�ika-sutta, where papañceti is taken in its sense as derived from Sanskrit prapañcayati ‘to describe at length’, from prapañca ‘diversity’. Back to text.[2] Robert Buswell has pointed out to me that Bhikkhu ÑÄ�ṇananda has arrived at the same conclusion. [ÑÄ�ṇananda 1971:31] Back to text.
[3] Without really
trying to second-guess the Tath�gata, the argument here is simply that
he might recognize a distinction in the semantics of aham asmi with
respect to his own description of the Enlightenment, and that of the
Ved�ntists. (He would almost certainly reject the use of such metaphor
for paedagogical purposes, however.) Jennings is right to point out that
the Ved�ntist schools and their concepts of, for example, m�y�,
contributed to the Buddha’s own teachings. [Jennings 1974:cix-cx]
Certainly, it can be said that useful comparison can be made between the
Buddhist and Ved�ntist traditions if such semantic differences are
reconciled. Fundamental unities are realized in the Buddhist tradition
at least insofar as the alienation of att�and anatt� are concerned (Cf. the remarks on bhavaṅga-sota above.). Back to text.
ReferencesAṅguttara-nik�ya. 1888. Aṅguttara-nik�ya. Vol. 2. Edited by Richard Morris. London: Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society. 6 vols. (1885-1910).Aṅguttara-nik�ya. 1933. The book of the Gradual Sayings. Vol. 2: The book of the Fours. Translated by F.L. Woodward. London: Oxford University Press for the Pali Text Society.
Buddhaghosa. 1936. Manorathapūraṇī: commentary on the Aṅguttara-nik�ya. Vol. 3. Edited by Hermann Kopp. London: Oxford University Press for the Pali Text Society. 5 vols. (1924-1956).
Childers, Robert Cæsar. 1875. A dictionary of the Pali language. London: Trübner & Co.
Jennings, J. G. 1974. The Ved�ntic Buddhism of the Buddha: a collection of historical texts translated [and edited] from the original P�li. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Reprint of 1947 ed.]
Majjhima-nik�ya.. 1888. Majjhima-nik�ya. Vol. 1. Edited by V. Trenckner. London: Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society. 4 vols. (1888-1925).
Mayrhofer, Manfred. 1951. Handbuch des P�li, mit Texten und Glossar:
eine Einführung in das sprachwissenschaftliche Studium des
Mittelindischen. 1. Teil: Grammatik. Heidelberg: Carl Winter Universitätsverlag.
Merrell-Wolff, Franklin. 1973 The philosophy of consciousness-without-an-object: reflections on the nature of transcendental consciousness. New York: Julian Press.
ÑÄ�ṇananda. 1971. Concept and reality in early Buddhist thought. Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society.
ÑÄ�ṇananda. 1974. The magic of the mind: an exposition of the KÄ�lakÄ�rÄ�ma-sutta. Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society.
Nyanatiloka. 1980. Buddhist dictionary: manual of Buddhist terms and doctrines. 4th edition, revised by Nyanaponika. Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society.
Paramatthajotik�. 1917. Sutta-nip�ta commentary: being Paramatthajotik� II. Vol. 2. Edited by Helmer Smith. London: Humphrey Milford for the Pali Text Society. 3 vols. (1916-1917).
Rhys Davies, T. W., and William Stede, eds. 1979. The Pali Text Society’s Pali-English dictionary. London: Pali Text Society. [Reprint of 1925 ed.]
Sa�yutta-nik�ya. 1890. Sa�yutta-nik�ya. Edited by Leon Feer. London: Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society. 3 vols. (1888-1890).
Sutta-nipÄ�ta. 1911. Die Reden Gotamo Buddhos aus der Sammlung der Bruchstücke SuttanipÄ�to des PÄ�li-Kanons. Translated by Karl Eugen Neumann. München: R. Piper & Co.
Sutta-nip�ta. 1913. Sutta-nip�ta. Edited by Dines Andersen and Helmer Smith. London: Henry Frowde for the Pali Text Society.
Sutta-nip�ta. 1944. Woven cadences of early Buddhists. Translated by E. M. Hare. London: Humphrey Milford for the Pali Text Society.
Sutta-nip�ta. 1985. The Sutta-nip�ta. Translated by Hammalava Saddhatissa. London: Curzon Press.
|
HTML Michael Everson, Evertype, Cnoc na Sceiche, Leac an Anfa, Cathair na Mart, Co. Mhaigh Eo, 2002-10-20 Copyright © 1993-2006 Evertype. All Rights Reserved
|
spam